I have just released a new channel on Youtube. It is called ‘The Philosophy of Psychiatric Diagnoses’. (https://www.youtube.com/@sfhps). I plan to make videos of academic presentations, make videos of academic papers and then just have more general discussion videos of ideas I have floating around.
Should neurodiversity be extended to animals?
In this blog post I consider whether the neurodiversity movement should be extended to animals. Neurodiversity is defined in many different ways but as a general characterisation I shall use this definition which is drawn from interviews with autistic adults. It “encompass[es] both human biological differences in cognition, brains, and genes while also serving as an activist tool for change toward acceptance and inclusion of autistic and other neurodivergent people” (Kapp 2020, p.viii, Autistic Community and the Neurodiversity Movement). So the question is whether this general notion should be restricted to humans or extended to some or all non-human animals.
A neurodiversity movement advocate could argue that all diversity is good. This seems to then entail that, given that they also have diverse brains, animals are also part of neurodiversity. We would have to extend our ethics to them. It seems this admittedly basic notion of neurodiversity seems to incorporate animals. I now consider if more developed notions of neurodiversity would exclude animals.
A neurodiversity movement advocate could argue that only forms of human diversity matter, therefore neurodiversity does not cover animals. There are two problems with this. Firstly, it seems arbitrary. What motivates that position compared to, say, neurodiversity should cover all humans except autistic people, or except schizophrenic people? What specifically makes humans important rather than any other grouping? Secondly, it is not clear that all human diversity is good. For example, it is unclear that sexual desires towards children has any positives. This approach to neurodiversity would exclude animals but it looks like a flawed approach.
A neurodiversity movement advocate might argue that only good forms of diversity matter and that only humans have good forms of diversity. Perhaps we might consider intelligence or ability to communicate as good types of diversity which animals lack. However, arguably some animals have higher intelligence and higher ability to communicate compared to some humans, so on this position we should extend the good type of diversity to those animals and not to some humans. So this also seems to not exclude animals from neurodiversity.
Some neurodiversity activists argue that diversity is a good thing in itself because it produces alternative ways of living, alternative characteristics and alternative views. Neurodiversity is consequently socially useful. Now, humans can generally get involved in society whereas it is not clear that animals are capable of getting involved in our society in any sort of analogous way. We can form a sort of friendship with animals but they cannot tell us about their unique opinion which we as non-human animals are unlikely to form. However, it is not clear that diversity is always a good thing given that some ways humans exist involve vast levels of harm (such as climate change and supporting economic systems which treat foreign labourers terribly). Also, it seems that we can learn from animals. Arguably, the most pressing issue we face today is climate change. It seems to me that we could learn from how animals interact with the environment and support sustainable ecosystems.
Perhaps there is a good reason to exclude animals from neurodiversity but this initial overview does not give any obvious reason to do so. As such, I think it should be a live option. I think that a neurodiversity advocate needs either give reason to restrict neurodiveristy to humans or should extend it to animals.
Extending neurodiversity to animals would mean we need radically rethink our relationship with animals. This means paying immense amounts of attention to the conditions animals live in when used for animal produce or meat. Put the words factory farm uk into youtube and you will see animals being treated in ways that seem to me as being incompatible with extending neurodiversity to them. Admittedly, I think there are immensely good ethical reasons to go vegan which have nothing to do with neurodiversity, namely animals being in pain in factory farms and the impact upon climate change caused from meat production, so I will hold these views reguardless of what follows from neurodiversity.
How should philosophy of psychiatry relate to the lived experience of service users?
Lancaster University Politics, Philosophy and Religion department runs a masters level module named What is Philosophy. On some weeks of the module a different philosopher within the department talk about their research and how it relates to more general questions about the nature of philosophy.
I did a session upon how philosophy of psychiatry relates to the lived experience of service users. Given my own background as an autistic individual who primarily researchers autism most my examples of services users related to individuals diagnosed as autistic. Within many different areas of philosophy there has been increased interest in broadening the evidence base of philosophy through incorporating the lived experience of a wider range of individuals, partly to move away from philosophy primarily being the domain of white, male, middle class individuals. There has been increasing interest in the lived experience of service users in philosophy of psychiatry, as is evident by multiple recent publications on epistemic injustice in psychiatry.
Questions relating to the correct application, limits and boundaries of philosophy are raised by this interest in lived experience. Lets assume, as I believe is uncontroversial, that there is value in broadening out the evidence basis of philosophy, such as by philosophers of psychiatry paying attention to what diagnosed people actually think about various issues with philosophical connotations. Philosophers might pay attention to whether diagnosed individuals thinks their diagnosis is pathological or not and pay attention to whether the diagnosed individual thinks their diagnosis accurately portrays how they actually are. However, once philosophers have considered what diagnosed individuals think then when can philosophers legitimately argue that the diagnosed individual is mistaken? When does philosophy of psychiatry have priority over service users on a philosophical issue or an issue with philosophical connotations?
One answer might be never. It could be argued that, for example, autistic people know what it is like to be autistic better than anyone else. Therefore, they are in an unique position to know whether autism is pathological and to know whether autism is a good diagnose compared to non-autistic people.
However, it is possible that lived experience has limits. Specifically, a demarcation can be made between the lived experience itself and forming concepts from the lived experience. It is possible that someone could have important lived experience and yet form unhelpful concepts from that lived experience. Perhaps someone has unhelpful implicit assumptions about the nature of health vs illness or what constitutes a good scientific concept when moving from their lived experience to forming concepts. Therefore, there could be room for philosophers of psychiatry to challenge the concepts which service users form without also challenging the lived experience itself.
It is possible that such a sharp demarcation between lived experience and concepts is untentable. Perhaps concepts might be required to understand experience (in a similar manner to how philosophers of science argue that observations are theory-laden). Therefore, lived experience might not always be so valuable if the person with the lived experience interprets it through flawed concepts. If so, this might give priority to philosophers. However, perhaps the sort of conceptual investigation which philosophers specialise in might itself be constrained by lived experience. Perhaps there are important concepts that philosophers are very unlikely to reach or understand, such as some concepts of what health is or what constitutes a good diagnosis, without the lived experience that is only present in diagnosed individuals. If so, this might give priority to service users.
Overall, I found the two hour session to be enjoyable and stimulating. I think these broader questions about the relationship between lived experience and philosophy is an undeveloped area. The development of epistemic injustice is important but I think more reflection is needed, at least within philosophy of psychiatry, upon what status lived experience should be given compared to philosophical reflection. Additionally, I suspect which should be given priority will probably be case specific rather than there being one rule which applies to all cases. Within my own research upon the status of psychiatric diagnoses I generally find drawing upon concepts from philosophy of science and highlighting them by drawing upon them examples from the history of psychiatry to be more valuable than drawing upon my lived experience of being autistic. That said, there are exceptions since I think the most interesting and important argument I have made was likely influenced by lived experience even if in the article I drew upon concepts in philosophy of science to make my argument (see The Value of Categorical, Polythetic Psychiatric Diagnoses” in British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, LINK , OPEN ACCESS LINK).
Can the causes of autism also cause depression or anxiety?
I have been following the reaction to the Spectrum 10K project by monitoring the #Spectrum10K and #StopSpectrum10K hashtags (Spectrum 10K is a project aiming to gather the DNA of 10,000 autistic individuals). I have often seen the claim that the depression and anxiety which many autistic individuals experience cannot be caused by autism. Therefore, if we want to reduce the level of depression and anxiety in autistic people there is no point studying the causes of autism. In this blog post I will analyse this claim.
It is commonly claimed that many autistic individuals have such high levels of depression and anxiety because our society does not accept them or accommodate them. Some people can be hostile to other people who are different and this rejection can have a negative impact upon those people who are different. Also, society is set up to accommodate some people whereas other people whom it is not set up for face many barriers in daily living. These claims seem correct. The question is whether the cause of autism could cause depression or anxiety in addition to the depression and anxiety caused by societal response. I will now outline two possible reasons for thinking the causes of autism can cause depression or anxiety.
In relation to non-autistic individuals, depression and anxiety can result from many factors. Some people get depressed or anxious because how their life is going. To say they get depressed or anxious due to their genes would be a mistake. However, other people get depressed or anxious even though there life appears to be going well. There is no detectable environmental trigger of the depression or anxiety. In these cases it is plausible to say that causes internal to the individual are causing the depression and anxiety. So this is an example of depression and anxiety occurring for reasons other than how their lives are going. Could the same sometimes happen in autistic individuals? Now, it could be claimed that if this is happening in autistic individuals then this is due to the causes of depression or anxiety and not the causes of autism. However, do we actually know this? Is it possible that some causes of autism play a causal role in the characteristics associated with autism and can separately also play a causal role in producing depression and anxiety? I do not think this can be ruled out. The sheer complexity of genetics is immense, with any particular gene potentially acting very differently depending upon which other genes are present and what environmental interactions occur. We have only a very limited understanding of this. So it is possible that the causes of autism actually do also result in depression or anxiety which arise irrespective of an individuals life situation. To be clear, I am not saying this is the case, rather, I am saying we do not know enough to rule out this being the case.
Another reason to question the claim that autism cannot cause depression and anxiety is the possibility that what we call depression and anxiety in autistic people is different to depression and anxiety in non-autistic people. When an autistic person reports that they are depressed, and when an non-autistic person reports that they are depressed we take them as to both be experiencing the same thing, namely depression. However, it is possible that actually the phenomenological experience (how it actually feels) of autistic individuals when they report depression is different to the phenomenological experience of non-autistic people when they report depression. This phenomenological experience could arise because what autistic individuals and non-autistic individuals report as depression actually stems from different causes. This would give reason to think that actually what is being reported as depression is actually different in both cases. All this could also be the case for anxiety. If what we call depression or anxiety in autistic people arises from the causes of autism then the causes of autism actually can cause depression or anxiety in autistic people. Now, is there any evidence for this claim? The problem is that phenomenology is very difficult to do and it is very rarely actually done today, so this is not the sort of thing which we have much evidence upon (although I have often felt that my experience of depression seems different to phenomenology I have read relating to non-autistic individuals). Additionally, it raises a whole bunch of metaphysical and conceptual issues about what make two things instances of the same thing (I have published a couple of papers which partly discuss this sort of issue in psychiatry, but ultimately philosophers have discussed these issues for literally multiple millennia in areas other than psychiatry). Seeing depression and anxiety as the same, or not the same, in autistic and non-autistic people seems to be compatible with the evidence and with credible metaphysical and conceptual approaches. Again, I am not suggesting it is the case that depression and anxiety are different in autistic and non-autistic individuals, rather, I am showing that it could be a possibility.
In this blog post I am doing philosophy, aiming to show alternative possibilities rather than showing a particular interpretation is true. I aim to show that we cannot simply dismiss or discount the claim that autism can cause depression or anxiety. As such, I think this is not grounds, in itself, to object to biological research on autism. Of course, I have not addressed many of the other potential problems with biological research on autism in general and Spectrum 10K in particular which may give good reason to reject Spectrum 10K (I have discussed some scientific problems with Spectrum 10K in another blog post).
The potential and pitfalls of Spectrum 10K
There has been a lot of hostility to the Spectrum 10K project on twitter. In this blog post I will reflect upon this, alongside mention some additional aspects of Spectrum 10K which I have not seen commented upon.
Some autistic people are against all biological investigation of autism. For example, they might think it is eugenicist, a waste of time or a far lower priority compared to changing society. So it makes sense that people with these views would reject Spectrum 10K. However, given the level of hostility to Spectrum 10K, it seems that lots more autistic individuals are against all biological research on autism than I realised or a lot of people think there are specific problems with Spectrum 10K which are not present in at least some other biological research on autism. It is the latter group I have in mind for this discussion.
One reason why I was surprised by the hostility is that Spectrum 10K seems less problematic than most biological research (which is not to say it is problem free, I will discuss problems below). Most biological research on autism aims to correlate biological factors with autism itself, i.e. with people who meet the diagnostic criteria. So far as I can see, Spectrum 10K is aiming to do something different. It aims to correlate biological factors present in autistic people with environmental factors. In this regard, Spectrum 10K is studying an area which is completely ignored by much biological research on autism. It is actually including the environment in scientific research. If you think, as I do, that issues of flourishing and disability ultimately involve both biology and the environment (and much besides them) then this is a good thing.
It opens a range of possible practical benefits compared to most biological research on autism. For example, imagine it was discovered that some biological factors are correlated with some sensory issues caused by particular environments. This could lead to two options. Firstly, change the environment. Secondly, develop a medication which specifically targets that biological factor, alleviating the sensory issue. Contrast Spectrum 10K’s approach with typical biological research on autism. It generally just finds endless biological complexity. But imagine if typical biological research on autism found a relatively strong biological factor present in most autistic people. What practical benefits could follow from this? It does not give us information about what part of the environment to change. It also means that any medication developed would probably affect lots of autistic individuals in a major way. That starts to look like a so called ‘cure for autism’ which so many autistic individuals are against. So it seems to me that Spectrum 10K has more likelihood of producing practical benefits and less likelihood of being eugenicist compared to most biological research on autism.
There are certainly significant potential issues with Spectrum 10K. Firstly, scientists have lots of sophisticated tools for investigating biological data. Are they going to use equally sophisticated tools for investigating the effect of the environment? They need make sure that they study a wide range of environmental factors and categorise those environmental factors in a nuanced way. They also need to understand how these environments affect autistic individuals through using sophisticated measurements of wellbeing and through understanding the phenomenological experience of autistic individuals. Secondly, Spectrum 10K will have much more statistical power compared to most biological studies given the sample size. This could be a significant positive but it also could cause more harm than good. A larger sample size can often drown out individual variation. It might only find commonalities at a broad level and miss smaller groupings of commonalties which only exist on a smaller scale within the sample size. Thirdly, there is the problem of epigenetics. Spectrum 10K will look at the relationship between biology and the environment, such as establishing that people with a specific gene have problems in a specific environment. However, another relationship is possible, namely that the environment might turn on the gene. So Spectrum 10K might mistake one causal relationship, biology plus environment resulting in lower wellbeing, for another, biology being present due to the environment and is unconnected to lower wellbeing. I do not know how Spectrum 10K will tackle these problems but certainly many studies are deficient in these matters.
Finally, some people think that, in contrast the claims of Spectrum 10K, that this data may end up in the hands of other organisations which will misuse it. This is a potential problem inherent in all biological research on autism. If anyone has any detail on what track record Cambridge has in relation to breaking promises or on data breaches, I would certainly be interested to read it.
Overall, if someone rejects all biological research on autism then it makes sense to reject Spectrum 10K. However, for all its potential problems, it seems to me a step in the right direction compared to most biological research on autism. It might, like most biological research, produce nothing of use. However, as much as I think we need to radically redress the balance of funding between biological investigation of autism compared to non-biological investigation, I do think this type of biological research has more potential than most biological research on autism.
Perspectivism and psychiatric diagnoses
My article ‘Perspectivism and Psychiatric Diagnoses: Respecting History and Constraining Relativism’ has been published in the European Journal for the Philosophy of Science (click for the open access article). I aimed to use a philosophy of science named scientific perspectivism to position psychiatric diagnoses as being between realism and relativism, that is, between psychiatric diagnoses being mind-independent entities out there waiting to be found and them being arbitrary conventions. I will outline my motives for writing the article in this blog post.
Psychiatric diagnoses have been described as being arbitrary, inventions and made-up. My article aims to defend psychiatric diagnoses from such claims by responding to one issue which motivates such claims. Historians and sociologists often provide detailed studies of how various social conditions and theoretical position lead psychiatrists to conceptualise psychiatric diagnoses in particular ways. If one set of social conditions, theoretical assumptions or methodological practices is present then psychiatrists will conceptualise psychiatric diagnoses within a range of ways but if a different set of social, theoretical and methodological factors is present then psychiatrists will conceptualise psychiatric diagnoses within yet another different set of ways. These factors do not determine which diagnoses psychiatrists formulate but they do influence and constrain which psychiatric diagnoses are formulated. For example, views about what constitute good mothering or good health could influence psychiatrists, as could theoretical factors such as whether psychology is seen to largely stem from underlining biology or from social interactions with the environment, as could whether focus goes upon finding statistical commonalities across many individuals or qualitative studies of individual people. This leads to the concern that psychiatric diagnoses reflect the opinions of psychiatrists, which have been heavily shaped by these factors, rather than reflect reality. Psychiatric diagnoses would not be real and instead only be the product of the wider social, theoretical or methodological factors in fashion in a particular period.
As a philosopher, I feel such an understanding potentially misses out something important. As a philosopher, my natural inclination is to say, yes, such factors can influence psychiatrists but the question of whether a scientific claim reflects reality is separate to question to why scientists believe that particular claim. A philosopher might tell these historians and sociologists that they have successfully documented the views that psychiatrists hold upon what exist but that is different to what actually exists. As a simple example, historians can document changing views that people have held about whether the earth is the centre of the universe or not but the views that astronomers hold does not then determine if the earth actually is at the centre of the universe. It can certainly be argued that psychiatrists being influenced changing social, theoretical and methodological factors make it unlikely that the psychiatric diagnoses they formulate reflect reality, but strictly speaking that is a point about how likely it is that psychiatrists are describing reality (an epistemological point) rather than a question of what exists (an ontological point).
However, as much as I am a philosopher, I also do historical research on psychiatry and I think philosophers need to take history seriously. I accept scientists are constrained by the historical context they work in but at the same time I also think that we should try to divide scientific claims into true, partly true and false. To do this I draw upon a philosophy of science named scientific perspectivism. This offers a more nuanced notion of truth and reality than either a common sense notion of ‘what things are really like’ or some form of essentialism. Following scientific perspectivism, I instead favour some sort of middle ground between ‘how things really are’ and the notion, seemingly favoured by some historians and sociologists, that all claims about truth (in psychiatry at least) are dependent upon wider social and historical factors. My motive for this is believing that some claims can be more truthful than others, some claims describe the external world better than others, yet no claim actually describes the external world as it is independent of our perspective.
One motive for my stance is that without it the legitimacy of science is potentially at threat. For example, if the beliefs of psychiatrists are constrained or heavily influenced in the era in which they work then their views seem to be the product of many subjective, rather than scientific, factors. Why should their beliefs have any higher legitimacy to the beliefs held by anyone else? Might psychiatry be literally on no better foundation than mere opinion and is no better established than the opinion of a random member of the public? Now, historians and sociologists typically do not endorse such a negative view of psychiatry but it is not clear to me what stops their position entailing such negative conclusions. As such, whilst I want to take seriously the influence of social factors on psychiatry, I think we need to still try and establish which claims are more truthful and which are less truthful. In the article I employ a philosophy of science to try and establish how philosophers can retain a non-trivial notion of truth whilst also respecting the influence of social, cultural, theoretical and methodological factors on psychiatry.
Report on subtyping autism workshop
On the 19th of November 2019 a workshop on subtyping autism was held at LSBU. The hosting organisation was PARC (Participatory Autism Research Collective). With help from individuals from PARC and LSBU, myself, Chloe Farahar and Annette Foster organised this workshop. The workshop lasted two and a half hours. There were five talks, each lasting twenty minutes followed by ten minutes of questions. Some papers argued against subtyping, some argued for subtyping and some looked at specific subtypes (or, in my own case, looked at multiple specific subtypes when I outlined the history of subtyping). I was pleased to see that the workshop was well attended, counting 37 people present at one point on a quick head count.
One aim of the workshop was to obtain the views of autistic people on the question of subtyping. I feel this was a success since some of the speakers identified as autistic whilst there were also autistic individuals in the audience. Some autistic people thought that questions about how to best formulate the diagnosis of autism should be largely determined by autistic people whereas other autistic people felt the views of autistic people should be one of many relevant factors. Either way, I hope this workshop went some way to facilitated autistic people, as well as the non-autistic, in providing views upon this issue.
Quite a number of speakers seemed to share a common vision of what a good psychiatric diagnosis should do, even though they disagreed about whether subtypes would help achieve those goals. In my presentation and in other presentations it was argued that there is more to autistic people than just a broadly defined autism. Rather, it is important to understand the specific ways in which a specific autistic person manifests autism (alongside understanding aspects of them unrelated to their diagnosis). Also, I and others argued that understanding how autistic people can change over time is important. It is also important to understand that different environments can influence how autistic people think, feel and behave. So in this reguard there was a level of shared commonality when it came to questions over what a good diagnostic system should do. Some people (including myself) felt that subtypes would help with understanding these factors whereas other felt this information could be best understood without subtyping autism.
I outlined a history of subtyping. I divided my history into three different areas, the 1930s to the 1970s, the 1980s until recently (around 2010) and finally I discussed the present day. I focused upon Lauretta Bender and Leo Kanner in the first period, then I focused upon DSM-III and Lorna Wing in the second period and finally I focused upon DSM-5 in the final period. I outlined how the subtypes which were employed heavily reflected the values held by psychiatrists in each era. I suggested that DSM-5 is still largely working within the values present in the 1980s even though our values are currently in a process of shifting away from those 1980s values. I then suggested that adopting subtypes would help better reflect the values we are currently moving towards.
The full list of talks was as follows:
Autistic observable and unobservable experiences, and erroneous subtyping: Introducing the Internal and External Autistic Space (Chloe Farahar & Annette Foster )
Exploring an autistic derived classification of autism (Mary Doherty)
Online discourse on autism does not need autism subtyping (Dafne Zuleima Morgado Ramirez)
An historical overview of subtyping (Sam Fellowes)
Demand Avoidance Phenomena: The circularity, integrity and validity of PDA: a commentary on the PDA Conference held by the National Autistic Society (2018) (Richard Woods)
Subtyping autism workshop
On the 19th of November (16.30 to 19.00 at London South Bank University (LSBU)) I am hosting (with collaborators) a workshop on subtyping autism. Below are some reasons why I am interested in this topic and more details on the event (note that these are reasons why I, rather than my collaborators or the presenters, am interested in the topic of subtyping).
My main academic interest is showing that psychiatric diagnoses are in principle scientifically legitimate. I argue that some (though not all) psychiatric diagnoses can be used in a similar way to how models are used in more respectable sciences. They cannot do everything a typical model can do in other sciences. Also, what they can do is usually done with less precision than occurs in other sciences. However, what level of similarity that they do have means that they have significant scientific worth (and this is true even though they typically cover a heterogeneous symptom picture and are causally heterogeneous).
Of course, psychiatric diagnoses can vary significantly in their scientific worth. Various ways of formulating them can impact this. The main diagnosis I am interested in is autism and one alternative way of formulating it is to add subtypes. This could alter its scientific worth as well as having many practical impacts outside of the scientific domain. This workshop will hopefully generate interesting discussion about these issues. Also, many speakers and attendees have a diagnosis of autism (or are in the process of being assessed) so lived experience might contribute some insight to both scientific and practical consequences of subtyping. Below is the initial abstract that was part of the call for papers and then the list of speakers.
This was the initial call for papers: Prior to and after the publication of the 2013 DSM there was much controversy over whether Asperger’s syndrome should be removed from the diagnostic manual. Members of the neurodiversity movement made contributions to this debate, drawing upon their lived experience of being autistic and their knowledge of the ways in which being diagnosed can be (or is not) beneficial. This conference aims to consider the question of autism and subtypes more broadly. What benefits or disadvantages are there for autistic people in adding substantive subtypes to autism? It is commonly stated that autistic people can present in many different ways. Might subtypes help add accuracy and nuance to clinical pictures? On the other hand, the boundaries between subtypes are typically vague and they can be placed in multiple places. This raises the danger that they are arbitrary impositions which do not reflect autistic experience. This conference draws upon the experience of autistic people to help resolve these issues. Possible areas for discussion include whether self-understanding for those diagnosed would be increased through being diagnosed with a more specific subtype or if this would unhelpfully impose unnatural constraints? Would the non-autistic be better able to understand different ways autism can manifest if there are significant subtypes, or would it help perpetuate unhelpful stereotypes based on an imposed limited number of ways autism would be proposed to manifest? Would the neurodiversity movement benefit from the subtypes bringing greater focus upon different ways autism can manifest or would this lead to unhelpful fracturing of the autistic community?
These are the papers that are being presented:
Autistic observable and unobservable experiences, and erroneous subtyping: Introducing the Internal and External Autistic Space (Chloe Farahar & Annette Foster )
Exploring an autistic derived classification of autism (Mary Doherty)
Online discourse on autism does not need autism subtyping (Dafne Zuleima Morgado Ramirez)
An historical overview of subtyping (Sam Fellowes)
Demand Avoidance Phenomena: The circularity, integrity and validity of PDA: a commentary on the PDA Conference held by the National Autistic Society (2018) (Richard Woods)
Reviewing Re-Thinking Autism
Re-Thinking Autism contains, to my knowledge, the most sustained attack upon the diagnosis of autism found within a single book. The editors claim it is the first book in the field of critical autism studies. It contains 17 different papers which are grouped into three areas, namely ‘What is autism’, ‘Deconstructing autism’ and ‘Challenging Practice’. The editors see critical autism studies as focusing on two questions. Firstly, is the diagnosis of autism valid and secondly, is it useful. Most articles are very critical of the diagnosis of autism. Since I felt I benefited immensely from being diagnosed with autism I was probably always going to have reservations. However, in the spirit of engaging with the critical autism studies movement, I will suggest that the book did not address some important questions and issues which would significantly help any attempted challenge to autism.
In relation to validity, multiple articles criticised the scientific foundations of autism. Some give an useful overview of the very heterogeneous causal underpinnings of autism. Whilst this is a very relevant point when assessing autism I feel the consequences were insufficiently explored. There were relatively few details about why the causal heterogeneity makes autism deeply flawed and in need of replacement. Some articles contain statements that autism is not a biological entity or a scientific entity but these are usually asserted rather than argued for. I think these claims face some challenges. Firstly, virtually all psychiatric diagnoses are causally heterogeneous. Therefore, I feel that critical autism studies scholars need either explain why autism need replacing whilst other diagnoses do not or need explicitly endorse a whole rejection of DSM type psychiatric diagnoses (perhaps in favour of person centred approaches). A few articles do seem closer to the latter approach though there are few explicit statements. Additionally, there is little discussion about why causal heterogeneity is problematic and why it makes something not a biological or scientific entity. There was also little mention of other important factors when assessing a scientific theory (such as simplicity, tractability or coherence). These are admittedly deeply philosophical questions which are debated by philosopher of psychiatry (and I was pleased to see a few articles reference philosophers of psychiatry) but I feel these are the sorts of questions which critical autism studies needs engage in. Perhaps the arguments which critical autism studies employ are fully defensible but they currently need more development.
In relation to usefulness, some articles question whether it is helpful to give people a label and other articles question whether it helps in educational settings or support settings. Some of these authors making these arguments have a wide range of experience and expertise. Consequently, I felt they had a viewpoint that was at minimum worth hearing. That said, there was very little input from people diagnosed with autism (only one author was described as being autistic). Very few of the reasons why I find being diagnosed so useful were mentioned. Of course, being autistic does not make me automatically correct on this issue. Perhaps my positive feelings about how useful being diagnosed was are based upon flawed reasoning. Despite this, it would have been good if the book engaged in reasons why some autistic people find being diagnosed so useful even if only to then challenge those reasons.
I feel the biggest problem was a lack of alternatives being outlined. If autism is deeply flawed then what should replace it? Even some vague suggestions (i.e. split it up, add subtypes, merge it with other diagnoses) would have been helpful if I am to assess whether an alternative to autism would be preferable. Additionally, outlining alternatives would give an easier route to challenge autism. There would be no need to argue autism is deeply flawed, rather, there would instead be the easier task of arguing that autism can be useful but an alternative diagnosis is even more useful.
It is worth nothing that the articles are quite diverse and so the degree to which these criticisms are applicable to any given article will vary significantly. Additionally, I felt around a quarter of the articles were pretty good (these were usually the ones which critically analysed autism rather than wished to replace the diagnosis).
To conclude, I felt many articles avoided important questions which are relevant for assessing scientific concepts. I would like to see the critical autism movement engage more with philosophy of science and philosophy of psychiatry. Also, it would be more helpful if criticisms of autism were also accompanied by actual concrete suggestions for alternatives to autism. Despite this, I am glad I bought it and read it. If you want a single book which contains multiple different criticisms of autism then this is the book to go for. I suspect I cite multiple articles from this volume (admittedly, mainly to criticise).
Ursula Le Guin (1929-2018), autism and neurodiversity
It was announced today that Ursula Le Guin died on the 22nd of January 2018. She was my favourite author in my late teens and early 20s whilst I put her in my top three today. I first read my favourite Le Guin novel, The Left Hand of Darkness, aged 18 and it probably had quite an influence on my thinking and views. To my knowledge, Le Guin never wrote about autism or neurodiversity but many of the themes in The Left Hand of Darkness seem very relevant.
The basic idea is a man from a western philosophy culture visits a world where the inhabitants are meant to be symbolic of eastern philosophy. The visitor sees things in contrastingly binary terms, such as light vs dark, society vs nature and male vs female. The world he visits has an eastern philosophy approach where different elements are in balance with one another, they do not form a sharp contrast. The strongest example is gender, since the inhabitants of this planet are genderless, so there is no binary contrast between male and female. However, the visitor, with his western philosophy, cannot help but put the inhabitants into binary terms of male and female, he struggles to shed his inbuilt preconceptions and see the inhabitants of the planet for how they truly are. The visitor constantly fails to read the motives of the inhabitants of the planet and often does not realise this is happening. However, during a political crisis which he also misreads he is eventually forced to cooperate with one of the inhabitants and, through a long and difficult process, eventually gain some insight into the inhabitants.
I read the novel as an exploration of the challenge of understanding others, be it people you have known all your life or people from cultures you are unfamilar with. I take Le Guin as thinking we often interpret people, especially people from other cultures, in unhelpful, simplistic, binary terms. She was influenced by her interest in anthropology and, writing in the late 1960s, the feminist movement which she made a major contribution to. These notions seems very important lessons for today given the existence of Donald Trump who characterises Mexican migrants as ‘rapists’ and African nations as ‘shitholes’ whilst ex-Daily Mail columnist Katie Hopkins describes migrants as ‘cockroaches’.
I think Le Guin’s general approach is also applicable to some of my interests in psychiatry. The problem of how to accurately understand someone who is different is quite central to philosophy of psychiatry. There has been a long history of negative connotations being associated with psychiatric patients and those in mental distress. As this articles shows, disability has often been associated with deviance and immorality. Whilst hopefully this situation is improved today, with more people talking about mental health, Le Guin’s insights are also important in a world which tries to be tolerant of those who are different. In relation to autism, modern science suggests autistic individuals often have unusual ways of thinking, unusual ways of perceiving the world and unusual ways of understanding others. Thus it is very easy for a non-autistic person to apply their non-autistic expectations to an autistic individual, think they have understood them but fail to. On the other hand, autistic people are not simply defined by the symptoms of autism, each one is a unique person with many unique traits and views. So there is an equal danger that a non-autistic person interprets an autistic person solely in terms them being autistic and thus again fail to understand who they are.
Additionally, all this is applicable from my perspective as an autistic person. Autistic people often struggle to pick up on social nuances or see the perspective of others, and these are certainly true of me. Additionally, my default position for many years was to assume people think and feel as I do but, in my experience, this just leads to typically failing to understand others without realising it. Of course, some autistic people go to considerable efforts to try see things from the non-autistic perspective but, in my experience at least, this is really difficult to do. Non-autistic people also have many diverse traits and views so this approach can easily lead to painting those around me with a big, rather inaccurate, brush.
Le Guin’s concerns over binary categories and importance of balance seems important here. She shows how, in relation to gender, we can find a helpful middle ground, a balance with more harmony if (primarily though not exclusively) men can make more effort to not hold unhelpful gender stereotypes and if both genders see that gender roles are a product of wider socio-cultural forces rather than how men and women truly are. Similarly, both autistic people and non-autistic people can try and find a helpful middle ground, that more harmonious balance. Even if most the problems are caused by the larger of two groups (the non-autistic) and even if many of those problems are caused by wider socio-cultural factors (such as misleading narratives from the media, expectations about what constitutes acceptable socialising or expectations that useful work must follow specific uniform procedures), I believe the best way to find that harmony is for both autistic people and non-autistic people to challenge the ways they perceive the other and where required make changes. This image of what neurodiversity should aim for is different to some notions of neurodiversity I have encountered which desire that only non-autistic people make changes. A mutual change towards more harmonious understanding feels to me more in line with the lessons of The Left Hand of Darkness, my favourite novel of the recently departed Ursula Le Guin.